Open Letter to the DSM-5
READ BELOW AND CLICK ON LINK TO SIGN:
http://www.ipetitions.com/petition/dsm5/
Sponsor
Society for Humanistic Psychology, Division 32 of the American Psychological Association,In alliance with:
--British Psychological Society (BPS),
--Danish Psychological Association,
--Division of Behavioral Neuroscience and Comparative Psychology (Division 6 of APA)
--Division of Developmental Psychology (Division 7 of APA),
--Division of Clinical Psychology (Division 12 of APA),
--Society of Counseling Psychology (Division 17 of APA)
--Society for Community Research and Action: Division of Community Psychology (Division 27 of APA),
--Division of Psychotherapy (Division 29 of APA),
--Society for the Psychology of Women (Division 35 of APA),
To the DSM-5 Task Force and the American Psychiatric Association:
As
you are aware, the DSM is a central component of the research,
education, and practice of most licensed psychologists in the United
States. Psychologists are not only consumers and utilizers of the
manual, but we are also producers of seminal research on DSM-defined
disorder categories and their empirical correlates. Practicing
psychologists in both private and public service utilize the DSM to
conceptualize, communicate, and support their clinical work.
For
these reasons, we believe that the development and revision of DSM
diagnoses should include the contribution of psychologists, not only as
select individuals on a committee, but as a professional community. We
have therefore decided to offer the below response to DSM-5 development.
This document was composed in recognition of, and with sensitivity to,
the longstanding and congenial relationship between American
psychologists and our psychiatrist colleagues.
Overview
Though
we admire various efforts of the DSM-5 Task Force, especially efforts
to update the manual according to new empirical research, we have
substantial reservations about a number of the proposed changes that are
presented on www.dsm5.org. As we will detail below, we are concerned
about the lowering of diagnostic thresholds for multiple disorder
categories, about the introduction of disorders that may lead to
inappropriate medical treatment of vulnerable populations, and about
specific proposals that appear to lack empirical grounding. In addition,
we question proposed changes to the definition(s) of mental disorder
that deemphasize sociocultural variation while placing more emphasis on
biological theory. In light of the growing empirical evidence that
neurobiology does not fully account for the emergence of mental
distress, as well as new longitudinal studies revealing long-term
hazards of standard neurobiological (psychotropic) treatment, we believe
that these changes pose substantial risks to patients/clients,
practitioners, and the mental health professions in general.
Given
the changes currently taking place in the profession and science of
psychiatry, as well as the developing empirical landscape from which
psychiatric knowledge is drawn, we believe that it is important to make
our opinions known at this particular historical moment. As stated at
the conclusion of this letter, we believe that it is time for psychiatry
and psychology collaboratively to explore the possibility of developing
an alternative approach to the conceptualization of emotional distress.
We believe that the risks posed by DSM-5, as outlined below, only
highlight the need for a descriptive and empirical approach that is
unencumbered by previous deductive and theoretical models.
In more detail, our response to DSM-5 is as follows:
Advances Made by the DSM-5 Task Force
We
applaud certain efforts of the DSM-5 Task Force, most notably efforts
to resolve the widening gap between the current manual and the growing
body of scientific knowledge on psychological distress. In particular,
we appreciate the efforts of the Task Force to address limitations to
the validity of the current categorical system, including the high rates
of comorbidity and Not Otherwise Specified (NOS) diagnoses, as well as
the taxonomic failure to establish ‘zones of rarity’ between purported
disorder entities (Kendell & Jablensky, 2003). We agree with the
APA/DSM-5 Task Force statement that, from a systemic perspective,
"The
DSM-III categorical diagnoses with operational criteria were a major
advance for our field, but they are now holding us back because the
system has not kept up with current thinking. Clinicians complain that
the current DSM-IV system poorly reflects the clinical realities of
their patients. Researchers are skeptical that the existing DSM
categories represent a valid basis for scientific investigations, and
accumulating evidence supports this skepticism." (Schatzberg, Scully,
Kupfer, & Regier, 2009)
As
researchers and clinicians, we appreciate the attempt to address these
problems. However, we have serious reservations about the proposed means
for doing so. Again, we are concerned about the potential consequences
of the new manual for patients and consumers; for psychiatrists,
psychologists, and other practitioners; and for forensics, health
insurance practice, and public policy. Our specific reservations are as
follows:
Lowering of Diagnostic Thresholds
The
proposal to lower diagnostic thresholds is scientifically premature and
holds numerous risks. Diagnostic sensitivity is particularly important
given the established limitations and side-effects of popular
antipsychotic medications. Increasing the number of people who qualify
for a diagnosis may lead to excessive medicalization and stigmatization
of transitive, even normative distress. As suggested by the Chair of
DSM-IV Task Force Allen Frances (2010), among others, the lowering of
diagnostic thresholds poses the epidemiological risk of triggering
false-positive epidemics.
We are particularly concerned about:
·
“Attenuated Psychosis Syndrome,”[1] which describes experiences common
in the general population, and which was developed from a “risk” concept
with strikingly low predictive validity for conversion to full
psychosis.
·
The proposed removal of Major Depressive Disorder’s[2] bereavement
exclusion, which currently prevents the pathologization of grief, a
normal life process.
·
The reduction in the number of criteria necessary for the diagnosis of
Attention Deficit Disorder,[3] a diagnosis that is already subject to
epidemiological inflation.
·
The reduction in symptomatic duration and the number of necessary
criteria for the diagnosis of Generalized Anxiety Disorder.[4]
Though
we also have faith in the perspicacity of clinicians, we believe that
expertise in clinical decision-making is not ubiquitous amongst
practitioners and, more importantly, cannot prevent epidemiological
trends that arise from societal and institutional processes. We believe
that the protection of society, including the prevention of false
epidemics, should be prioritized above nomenclatural exploration.
Vulnerable Populations
We
are also gravely concerned about the introduction of disorder
categories that risk misuse in particularly vulnerable populations. For
example, Mild Neurocognitive Disorder[5] might be diagnosed in elderly
with expected cognitive decline, especially in memory functions.
Additionally, children and adolescents will be particularly susceptible
to receiving a diagnosis of Disruptive Mood Dysregulation Disorder[6] or
Attenuated Psychosis Syndrome. Neither of these newly proposed
disorders have a solid basis in the clinical research literature, and
both may result in treatment with neuroleptics, which, as growing
evidence suggests, have particularly dangerous side-effects (see
below)—as well as a history of inappropriate prescriptions to vulnerable
populations, such as children and the elderly
Sociocultural Variation
The
DSM-5 has proposed to change the Definition of a Mental Disorder such
that DSM-IV’s Feature E: “Neither deviant behavior (e.g., political,
religious, or sexual) nor conflicts that are primarily between the
individual and society are mental disorders unless the deviance or
conflict is a symptom of a dysfunction in the individual,”[7] will
instead read “[A mental disorder is a behavioral or psychological
syndrome or pattern] [t]hat is not primarily a result of social deviance
or conflicts with society.”[8] The latter version fails to explicitly
state that deviant behavior and primary conflicts between the individual
and society are not mental disorders. Instead, the new proposal focuses
on whether mental disorder is a “result” of deviance/social conflicts.
Taken literally, DSM-5’s version suggests that mental disorder may be
the result of these factors so long as they are not “primarily” the
cause. In other words, this change will require the clinician to draw on
subjective etiological theory to make a judgment about the cause of
presenting problems. It will further require the clinician to make a
hierarchical decision about the primacy of these causal factors, which
will then (partially) determine whether mental disorder is said to be
present. Given lack of consensus as to the “primary” causes of mental
distress, this proposed change may result in the labeling of
sociopolitical deviance as mental disorder.
Revisions to Existing Disorder Groupings
Several new proposals with little empirical basis also warrant hesitation:
Several new proposals with little empirical basis also warrant hesitation:
·
As mentioned above, Attenuated Psychosis Syndrome[9] and Disruptive
Mood Dysregulation Disorder (DMDD)[10] have questionable diagnostic
validity, and the research on these purported disorders is relatively
recent and sparse.
·
The proposed overhaul of the Personality Disorders[11] is perplexing.
It appears to be a complex and idiosyncratic combined
categorical-dimensional system that is only loosely based on extant
scientific research. It is particularly concerning that a member of the
Personality Disorders Workgroup has publicly described the proposals as
“a disappointing and confusing mixture of innovation and preservation of
the status quo that is inconsistent, lacks coherence, is impractical,
and, in places, is incompatible with empirical facts” (Livesley, 2010),
and that, similarly, Chair of DSM-III Task Force Robert Spitzer has
stated that, of all of the problematic proposals, “Probably the most
problematic is the revision of personality disorders, where they’ve made
major changes; and the changes are not all supported by any empirical
basis.”[12]
·
The Conditions Proposed by Outside Sources[13] that are under
consideration for DSM-5 contain several unsubstantiated and questionable
disorder categories. For example, “Apathy Syndrome,” “Internet
Addiction Disorder,” and “Parental Alienation Syndrome” have virtually
no basis in the empirical literature.
New Emphasis on Medico-Physiological Theory
Advances
in neuroscience, genetics, and psychophysiology have greatly enhanced
our understanding of psychological distress. The neurobiological
revolution has been incredibly useful in conceptualizing the conditions
with which we work. Yet, even after “the decade of the brain,” not one
biological marker (“biomarker”) can reliably substantiate a DSM
diagnostic category. In addition, empirical studies of etiology are
often inconclusive, at best pointing to a diathesis-stress model with
multiple (and multifactorial) determinants and correlates. Despite this
fact, proposed changes to certain DSM-5 disorder categories and to the
general definition of mental disorder subtly accentuate biological
theory. In the absence of compelling evidence, we are concerned that
these reconceptualizations of mental disorder as primarily medical
phenomena may have scientific, socioeconomic, and forensic consequences.
New emphasis on biological theory can be found in the following DSM-5
proposals:
·
The first of DSM-5’s proposed revisions to the Definition of a Mental
Disorder transforms DSM-IV’s versatile Criterion D: “A manifestation of a
behavioral, psychological, or biological dysfunction in the
individual”[14] into a newly collapsed Criterion B: [A behavioral or
psychological syndrome] “That reflects an underlying psychobiological
dysfunction.”[15] The new definition states that all mental disorders
represent underlying biological dysfunction. We believe that there is
insufficient empirical evidence for this claim.
·
The change in Criterion H under “Other Considerations” for the
Definition of a Mental Disorder adds a comparison between medical
disorders and mental disorders with no discussion of the differences
between the two. Specifically, the qualifying phrase “No definition
adequately specifies precise boundaries for the concept of ‘mental
disorder’”[16] was changed to “No definition perfectly specifies precise
boundaries for the concept of either ’medical disorder’ or
‘mental/psychiatric disorder’.”[17][18] This effectively transforms a
statement meant to clarify the conceptual limitations of mental disorder
into a statement equating medical and mental phenomena.
·
We are puzzled by the proposals to “De-emphasize medically unexplained
symptoms” in Somatic Symptom Disorders (SSDs) and to reclassify
Factitious Disorder as an SSD. The SSD Workgroup explains: “…because of
the implicit mind-body dualism and the unreliability of assessments of
‘medically unexplained symptoms,’ these symptoms are no longer
emphasized as core features of many of these disorders.”[19] We do not
agree that hypothesizing a medical explanation for these symptoms will
resolve the philosophical problem of Cartesian dualism inherent in the
concept of “mental illness.” Further, merging the medico-physical with
the psychological eradicates the conceptual and historical basis for
somatoform phenomena, which are by definition somatic symptoms that are
not traceable to known medical conditions. Though such a redefinition
may appear to lend these symptoms a solid medico-physiological
foundation, we believe that the lack of empirical evidence for this
foundation may lead to practitioner confusion, as might the stated
comparison between these disorders and research on cancer,
cardiovascular, and respiratory diseases.[20]
·
The proposed reclassification of Attention Deficit/Hyperactivity
Disorder (ADHD) from Disorders Usually First Diagnosed in Infancy,
Childhood, or Adolescence to the new grouping “Neurodevelopmental
Disorders” seems to suggests that that ADHD has a definitive
neurological basis. This change, in combination with the proposal to
lower the diagnostic threshold for this category as described above,
poses high risk of exacerbating the extant over-medicalization and
over-diagnosis of this disorder category.
·
A recent publication by the Task Force, The Conceptual Evolution of
DSM-5 (Regier, Narrow, Kuhl, & Kupfer, 2011), states that the
primary goal of DSM-5 is “to produce diagnostic criteria and disorder
categories that keep pace with advances in neuroscience.”[21] We believe
that the primary goal of DSM-5 should be to keep pace with advances in
all types of empirical knowledge (e.g., psychological, social, cultural,
etc.).
Taken
together, these proposed changes seem to depart from DSM’s 30-year
“atheoretical” stance in favor of a pathophysiological model. This move
appears to overlook growing disenchantment with strict neurobiological
theories of mental disorder (e.g., “chemical imbalance” theories such as
the dopamine theory of schizophrenia and the serotonin theory of
depression), as well as the general failure of the neo-Kraepelinian[22]
model for validating psychiatric illness. Or in the words of the Task
Force:
“…epidemiological,
neurobiological, cross-cultural, and basic behavioral research
conducted since DSM-IV has suggested that demonstrating construct
validity for many of these strict diagnostic categories (as envisioned
most notably by Robins and Guze) will remain an elusive goal” (Kendler,
Kupfer, Narrow, Phillips, & Fawcett, 2009, p. 1).
We
thus believe that a move towards biological theory directly contradicts
evidence that psychopathology, unlike medical pathology, cannot be
reduced to pathognomonic physiological signs or even multiple
biomarkers. Further, growing evidence suggests that though psychotropic
medications do not necessarily correct putative chemical imbalances,
they do pose substantial iatrogenic hazards. For example, the
increasingly popular neuroleptic (antipsychotic) medications, though
helpful for many people in the short term, pose the long-term risks of
obesity, diabetes, movement disorders, cognitive decline, worsening of
psychotic symptoms, reduction in brain volume, and shortened lifespan
(Ho, Andreasen, Ziebell, Pierson, & Magnotta, 2011; Whitaker, 2002,
2010). Indeed, though neurobiology may not fully explain the etiology of
DSM-defined disorders, mounting longitudinal evidence suggests that the
brain is dramatically altered over the course of psychiatric treatment.
Conclusions
In
sum, we have serious reservations about the proposed content of the
future DSM-5, as we believe that the new proposals pose the risk of
exacerbating longstanding problems with the current system. Many of our
reservations, including some of the problems described above, have
already been articulated in the formal response to DSM-5 issued by the
British Psychological Society (BPS, 2011) and in the email communication
of the American Counseling Association (ACA) to Allen Frances (Frances,
2011b).
In light of the above-listed reservations concerning DSM-5’s proposed changes, we hereby voice agreement with BPS that:
•
“…clients and the general public are negatively affected by the
continued and continuous medicalization of their natural and normal
responses to their experiences; responses which undoubtedly have
distressing consequences which demand helping responses, but which do
not reflect illnesses so much as normal individual variation.”
•
“The putative diagnoses presented in DSM-V are clearly based
largely on social norms, with 'symptoms' that all rely on subjective
judgments, with little confirmatory physical 'signs' or evidence of
biological causation. The criteria are not value-free, but rather
reflect current normative social expectations.”
•
“… [taxonomic] systems such as this are based on identifying
problems as located within individuals. This misses the relational
context of problems and the undeniable social causation of many such
problems.”
•
There is a need for “a revision of the way mental distress is thought
about, starting with recognition of the overwhelming evidence that it is
on a spectrum with 'normal' experience” and the fact that strongly
evidenced causal factors include “psychosocial factors such as poverty,
unemployment and trauma.”
•
An ideal empirical system for classification would not be based on past
theory but rather would “ begin from the bottom up – starting with
specific experiences, problems or ‘symptoms’ or ‘complaints’.”
The
present DSM-5 development period may provide a unique opportunity to
address these dilemmas, especially given the Task Force’s willingness to
reconceptualize the general architecture of psychiatric taxonomy.
However, we believe that the proposals presented on www.dsm5.org are
more likely to exacerbate rather than mitigate these longstanding
problems. We share BPS’s hopes for a more inductive, descriptive
approach in the future, and we join BPS in offering participation and
guidance in the revision process.
References
American Psychiatric Association (2011). DSM-5 Development. Retrieved from http://www.dsm5.org/Pages/Default.aspx
British
Psychological Society. (2011) Response to the American Psychiatric
Association: DSM-5 development. Retrieved from
http://apps.bps.org.uk/_publicationfiles/consultationresponses/DSM-5%202011%20-%20BPS%20response.pdf
Compton,
M. T. (2008). Advances in the early detection and prevention of
schizophrenia. Medscape Psychiatry & Mental Health. Retrieved from
http://www.medscape.org/viewarticle/575910
Frances, A. (2010). The first draft of DSM-V. BMJ. Retrieved from http://www.bmj.com/content/340/bmj.c1168.full
Frances,
A. (2011a). DSM-5 approves new fad diagnosis for child psychiatry:
Antipsychotic use likely to rise. Psychiatric Times. Retrieved from
http://www.psychiatrictimes.com/display/article/10168/1912195
Frances,
A. (2011b). Who needs DSM-5? A strong warning comes from professional
counselors [Web log message]. Psychology Today. Retrieved from
http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/dsm5-in-distress/201106/who-needs-dsm-5
Hanssen, M., Bak, M., Bijl, R., Vollebergh, W., & van Os, J. (2005). The incidence and outcome
of subclinical psychotic experiences in the general population. British Journal of Clinical
Psychology, 44, 181-191.
of subclinical psychotic experiences in the general population. British Journal of Clinical
Psychology, 44, 181-191.
Ho,
B-C., Andreasen, N. C., Ziebell, S., Pierson, R., & Magnotta, V.
(2011). Long-term antipsychotic treatment and brain volumes. Archives of
General Psychiatry, 68, 128-137.
Johns,
L. C., & van Os, J. (2001). The continuity of psychotic experiences
in the general population. Clinical Psychology Review, 21, 1125-1141.
Kendell,
R., & Jablensky, A. (2003). Distinguishing between the validity and
utility of psychiatric diagnoses. The American Journal of Psychiatry,
160, 4-11.
Kendler,
K., Kupfer, D., Narrow, W., Phillips, K., & Fawcett, J. (2009,
October 21). Guidelines for making changes to DSM-V. Retrieved August
30, 2011, from
http://www.dsm5.org/ProgressReports/Documents/Guidelines-for-Making-Changes-to-DSM_1.pdf
Livesley,
W. J. (2010). Confusion and incoherence in the classification of
Personality Disorder: Commentary on the preliminary proposals for DSM-5.
Psychological Injury and Law, 3, 304-313.
Moran, M. (2009). DSM-V developers weigh adding psychosis risk. Psychiatric News Online.
Retrieved from http://psychnews.psychiatryonline.org/newsarticle.aspx?articleid=112801
Retrieved from http://psychnews.psychiatryonline.org/newsarticle.aspx?articleid=112801
Regier,
D. A., Narrow, W. E., Kuhl, E. A., & Kupfer, D. J. (2011). The
conceptual evolution of DSM-5. Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric
Publishing.
Schatzberg, A. F., Scully, J. H., Kupfer, D. J., & Regier, D. A. (2009). Setting the record
straight: A response to Frances commentary on DSM-V. Psychiatric Times, 26. Retrieved from http://www.psychiatrictimes.com/dsm/content/article/10168/1425806
straight: A response to Frances commentary on DSM-V. Psychiatric Times, 26. Retrieved from http://www.psychiatrictimes.com/dsm/content/article/10168/1425806
Whitaker,
R. (2002). Mad in America. Cambridge, MA: Basic Books. Also see
http://www.madinamerica.com/madinamerica.com/Schizophrenia.html
Whitaker, R. (2010). Anatomy of an epidemic. New York, NY: Random House.
No comments:
Post a Comment
PLEASE ADD COMMENTS SO I CAN IMPROVE THE INFORMATION I AM SHARING ON THIS VERY IMPORTANT TOPIC.